The Blank Slate: Steven Pinker Stuck in the Seventies
Steven Pinker became a celebrity when he published How the Mind Works, a book that explains the human mind using evolutionary biology (which explains why we evolved the emotional biases and intellectual capabilities that we have) and cognitive science (which uses computer models to explain human thought). It is an excellent book that is about 95% science and is only about 5% physicalist dogma claiming that there is nothing to the human mind except what these sciences can explain.
Once
you are a celebrity, publishers are eager to bring out anything you write.
Pinker continued to write some books that explain his scientific work to the
public, such as The Language Instinct. But he was also able to publish works
that are more dogma than science.
The
most dogmatic is The Blank Slate. This diffuse, disorganized book devotes some
time to Pinker's valuable scientific work, but it devotes much more time to
Pinker's amateurish attempts at philosophy and to political opinions that he formed
in the 1970s and has not rethought since.
Beating Dead Horses
Pinker
begins the book by saying that colleagues always told him that he was beating a
dead horse when he told them that he was working on a book about the theory
that the mind is a blank slate that our experience writes upon, a theory that
goes back to the seventeenth-century writings of John Locke. No, Pinker says,
it is still central to the intellectual debate today.
But the
first example he discusses at length to show that the blank slate is still
central is behaviorist psychology-the theory, most famously expounded by B.F.
Skinner, that our behavior is entirely the result of conditioning and not of
human nature. Skinner believed that we could condition people to produce a
utopian society, and he replied to criticism that he would reduce human freedom
by saying we are already the products of conditioning, so we are "beyond
freedom and dignity."
This is
an unfortunate way for Pinker to make his point that the blank slate is central
to today's intellectual debates, because the influence of behaviorist
psychology peaked in the 1950s and 1960s, and virtually no one believes in it
today. Today, the most common theory among the public is that our psychology
depends on brain chemistry-which is why we try to restore the normal chemical
balance in the brain by giving Ritalin to school children and Prozac to adults.
How can Pinker possibly use behaviorism to show that the blank slate is
important today?
Pinker
also argues for the relevance of this book by providing a long series of
quotations from anthropologists who are cultural relativists, claiming that
every culture is equally valid because there is no human nature, just a blank
slate. Yet the quotations range from the 1930s through the 1970s. The influence
of this sort of thinking has declined dramatically in the face of evolutionary
psychology, which shows that there is an evolved human nature. How can Pinker
use a series of quotations that ends in the 1970s to show that the blank slate
is important today?
Radical Marxists and Feminists
The
reason becomes clear later in the book, when Pinker begins to talk about his
own personal introduction to these issues: Pinker is still fighting against the
ideas that were popular when he was a graduate student in the 1970s.
At that
time, politics in the academy was dominated by Marxists, who believed there is
no human nature and our behavior is the result of economic factors, and by
radical feminists, who believed there is no human nature and that differences
between men and women are purely the result of social stereotypes. Pinker
compares these thinkers to modernist urban planners, such as Le Corbusier, who
created utopian designs for cities that failed because they ignored human
nature. In later chapters of the book, he adds deconstructionists to the crew
he attacks.
Yet the
influence of these schools of thought among academics peaked in the 1970s. The
influence of Marxism has waned dramatically since the collapse of communism in
eastern Europe in 1989, and the influence of the most extreme radical feminists
has waned dramatically since feminism entered the mainstream. The influence of
modernist planning in the style of Le Corbusier peaked in the 1960s, and today
modernist planning has been eclipsed by New Urbanism, with its neo-traditional
urban design. As one sign of this change, over 96,000 units of public housing
in the modernist style were torn down under the federal government's HOPE VI
program and replaced with neo-traditional urban neighborhoods.
Pinker
is quite right to say that these schools of thought are dehumanizing. He is
particularly good in later chapters of the book, where he adds
deconstructionism to the enemies' list and refutes it using his own theories
about language rather than just attacking his opponents rhetorically. But
throughout, he is beating horses that are either dead or dying:
deconstructionism was still on the rise in the 1970s, but its influence peaked
in the 1980s and has been declining since.
He
complains about scientists who wanted to make their work serve "hard-left
ideology," some calling themselves the "radical science
movement," and his leading example is the first lecture he attended as an
graduate student at Harvard in 1976. It was true in the 1970s, but how many
scientists are there today who say they are part of the "radical science
movement"?
1970s Environmentalists
Environmentalists
were also very influential when Pinker was a graduate student, and in The Blank
Slate, he parrots conventional conservative arguments against environmentalism,
focusing on environmental issues that were current in the 1970s and ignoring
those that are most important today.
He
attacks environmentalists for what he calls their "Malthusian"
predictions that there are limits on resources, criticizing the Club of Rome
Report named The Limits of Growth, which focused national attention on the
issue when it was published in 1972. To refute this report, he mentions the
famous wager between Paul Ehrlich, an early environmentalist, and Julian Simon,
a fellow at the free market Cato Institute, about whether the price of natural
resources would rise in real terms between 1980 and 1990; they bet about the
price of five strategic metals, and Ehrlich lost all five bets, because (Pinker
says) "Malthusian prophesies ignore the effect of technological change in
increasing the resources that support a comfortable life." Pinker mentions
in passing that The Limits of Growth said that uncontrolled growth would
ultimately cause both resource shortages and more pollution than the earth
could absorb-but he goes on to ignore pollution and only discuss resources.
Yet
elementary economics tells us that the free market gives businesses an
incentive to increase the supply of a resource when shortages drive its price
up, but that the market has no mechanism that gives businesses an incentive to
reduce pollution. Environmentalists are clearly right to say that government
must control pollution. In 1990, the United States set up a cap-and-trade
program to reduce the emissions that caused acid rain, and it worked: acid rain
is no longer killing our forests and lakes, as it was in the 1980s. By the time
Pinker wrote The Blank Slate, environmentalists considered global warming to be
the greatest environmental threat and were calling for cap-and-trade to control
it also. In fact, California passed a law using cap-and-trade to control
greenhouse gas emissions just four years after this book was published.
When it
comes to global warming and other problems caused by pollution, Pinker is
clearly wrong to attack environmentalists and claim that new technology in
itself will solve the problems. Yes, we do need to develop new clean energy
technologies to control global warming, but the market does not provide the incentive
needed to shift to clean energy quickly enough. It will remain cheaper for
quite a while to keep existing dirty power plants than to replace them with
clean energy, so we need the government to provide incentives to shift to clean
energy in time to avoid the worst effects of global warming. The entire world
realizes this, with the exception of the Trump administration, which is why the
world adopted the Paris agreement in 2016 and governments worldwide pledged to
limit greenhouse gas emissions.
This is
elementary economic theory-the market does not account for what economists call
"externalities"-but Pinker simply ignores it and keeps repeating the
claim that technology alone will solve our problems.
Pinker
attacks environmentalists of the 1970s, such as Paul Ehrlich and the Club of
Rome, and he ignores what environmentalists are saying today. The resource
shortages and economic disruption of the 1970s led many environmentalists to be
overly pessimistic during that decade and to think that environmental crisis
was inevitable. Today, as we face the problem of global warming, most
environmentalists are guardedly optimistic: we can avoid the worst effects of
climate change if world governments can agree to limit greenhouse gas emissions
and to transition to clean energy, as they did in the Paris Agreement, and then
can move quickly enough to limit emissions. Yet the Paris agreement would never
have been signed if we listened to the right-wing slogan that we do not need to
control pollution because technology will solve all our problems.
Since
global warming is the biggest environmental issue that the world faces today
and was the biggest at the time he wrote, we would expect Pinker to look at
what environmentalists say about this issue, rather than focusing on what Paul
Ehrlich and the Club of Rome were saying during the 1970s. With the
overwhelming majority all climate scientists agreeing that human-caused global
warming is a significant threat, we would expect Pinker to look at scientific
evidence and economic realities that exist today, but instead he restates the
political prejudices that he formed in the 1970s.
Materialist Moral Philosophy
Though
his philosophy is amateurish, Pinker does know more about the subject than most
evolutionary psychologists, and he does a better job of justifying morality
than the usual account of how altruism evolves. He understands how altruism
evolved, but he also understands that he would be committing the naturalistic
fallacy if he tried to justify morality on the basis of how it evolved.
Instead,
he justifies morality by reproducing a Calvin and Hobbes cartoon where Calvin
says he does not believe in morality and Hobbes shoves him so he falls in the
mud. Pinker comments:
The
brain may be a physical system made of ordinary matter, but that matter is
organized in such a way as ... to feel pleasure and pain. And that in turn sets
the stage for the emergence of morality. ... since one is better off not
shoving and not getting shoved than shoving and getting shoved, it pays to
insist on a moral code, even if the price is adhering to itself oneself."
Pinker
is saying that morality is a matter of expediency: we want to have pleasure and
avoid pain, and we invent morality because it helps us get what we want,
sacrificing some pleasures to avoid greater pains. This is similar to the
social contract theory of philosophers beginning with Hobbes. It is also
similar to the evolutionary psychologists' theory of reciprocal altruism, but
it presented in a way that justifies morality rather than explaining how it
evolved. Yet there are obvious problems with this theory.
If
morality is just a matter of expediency, then it makes sense to cheat. If I go
along with my society's morality just because it helps me to get pleasure and avoid
pain, then I will also cheat if it helps me to get pleasure and avoid pain. In
most cases, I will not cheat, because being detected would hurt my reputation
and make my life less pleasant, but if I am sure that my cheating will never be
detected (or if I think the benefits of cheating outweigh the risk of being
detected) then I will cheat.
If
morality is just a matter of expediency, then I will not help the poor and
powerless unless it also helps me. The powerless generally cannot retaliate for
any damage I do to them and cannot repay me adequately for any benefits I give
them. I will help them only if I think it will make my own life better by
giving me a reputation for charity, which will make people admire me and will
make my own life more pleasant.
If
morality is just a matter of expediency, then it does not apply to people
outside of my society. I go along with my society's morality because my life
will be more pleasant if everyone I encounter accepts this morality, but if my
society discovers some new part of the world where primitive people live, then
I will decide what to do with those people by asking myself whether my own life
will be more pleasant if my group treats them morally or if my group enslaves
or exterminates them.
If
morality is just a matter of expediency, then it certainly does not apply to
animals. Animals cannot join in the social contract by accepting society's
morality, so there is no benefit to me in treating animals kindly. I will treat
them in the way that is most expedient for me, and if treating animals cruelly
saves me a bit of money when I buy food, that is what I will do. Why should I
do anything for animals, when animals will not do anything for me in return?
Notice
that all of these examples talk about what I "will" do, rather than
about what I "ought" to do. Pinker understands the naturalistic
fallacy, so he should agree with me that, if ethics is based on expediency, it
is logically impossible to get from "is" to "ought." It "is"
true that I desire to have pleasure and to avoid pain and that I am more likely
to satisfy this desire if my society has a moral code, but it is impossible to
get from those "is" statements to the statements that I ought to obey
the moral code.
Epicurus,
the earliest materialist philosopher whose writing survives, was the first to
advocate Pinker's idea that morality is just a matter of expediency. Like
Pinker, he believed that only matter exists, that we try to seek pleasure and
avoid pain, and that we invent morality as a matter of expediency, to avoid
being harmed by others.
Despite
all of his scientific knowledge, Pinker is not able to do a better job of
justifying morality than Epicurus did over two millennia ago. No materialist
can. They can only appeal to expediency, because they live in a world of
"is statements" where there cannot be any justification for
"ought statements."
Physicalism and Freedom
Pinker
blames the blank slate for the totalitarian ideologies of Marxism and radical
feminism: if there is no human nature, then we can manipulate people in any way
that is needed to reach our utopian goals. He doesn't mention that John Locke,
his earliest example of the blank slate, inspired the liberal ideals of the
American Revolution-that Jefferson had a bust of and Locke in his study and
based the argument of the Declaration of Independence on Locke's ideas.
As
usual, Pinker's argument is out of date. Utopians used to claim that there was
no limit to their ability to manipulate people because there was no human
nature, but the technology being developed today gives us more power over
nature. Even if there is a human nature, utopian totalitarians can potentially
use drugs and genetic engineering to change human nature.
Totalitarians
potentially have much more power than they had in the past. In the past, they
ignored human nature, so their utopias ultimately failed, as Pinker says.
Today, they are on the edge of being able to manipulate human nature to make
humanity fit into their utopias.
In the
days of B.F. Skinner and the behaviorists, educators talked about conditioning
children, but today, educators are more likely to get drug prescriptions for
children: instead of trying to condition children who are disruptive, they say
the children have Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD) and give them
prescriptions for Ritalin. Some children can benefit from psychiatric drugs,
but the fact that we in the United States prescribe psychiatric drugs more than
twice as often as the Netherlands and more than three times as often as Germany
shows that we are over-using drugs to control children who do not fit in.
Utopian
totalitarians will welcome new drugs that control behavior more effectively and
will also want to use genetic engineering to change human nature. How can we
justify resistance to these new forms of totalitarianism?
The
usual justification is that controlling people in these ways would violate
their freedom, but Pinker says explicitly that we have no freedom, and our
behavior is determined.
He
spends a chapter of The Blank Slate talking about the conflict between
determinism and free will. He says that his physicalism is deterministic, but
we should not worry about determinism because it does not undermine personal
responsibility. We make people responsible for their actions, for example, by
punishing criminals, and people take these consequences into account when they
plan their actions. The possibility of punishment is one of the factors that
determines their behavior, so they are held responsible for their behavior even
though it is determined.
But he
does not notice a deeper implication of his view: if we are nothing more than
computers whose behavior is determined, rather than humans who have freedom,
then we can no longer say that utopians who control our behavior are violating
our freedom.
It is
odd that Pinker believes in determinism, which is based on classical physics,
rather than seeing that modern physics allows for randomness as well as
determinism. We have seen that Daniel Dennett uses twentieth-century physics to
argue that freedom is worthless, because it can only be random behavior, which
is no better than determined behavior. By contrast, Pinker sticks with the old
debate between freedom and determinism, based on the nineteenth-century physics.
This is one more example of how amateurish his philosophy is.
Either
way, physicalists like Pinker or Dennett do not believe in freedom, so they do
not believe in the most important reason to resist totalitarian use of drugs
and genetic engineering. Our minds are just evolved computers, so why shouldn't
redesign and improve them, just as we constantly redesign and improve the
computers on our desktop?
A
dualist or new-physics materialist can believe that evolution took advantage of
some unknown property of matter to create freedom-the ability to make
deliberate decisions-and can believe that freedom is so valuable that we should
not allow utopian social planners to control us. But physicalists do not
believe in freedom. Though Pinker himself seems to be a decent person who would
resist totalitarianism, he is promoting a theory that implies there is nothing
wrong with totalitarian control of human behavior.
In The
Blank Slate, he argues at length for genetic engineering of food, and some of
arguments would also support genetic engineering of people. It seems that he
overlooks human genetic engineering because it is unthinkable in our
society-but if our society accepted Pinker's physicalism, human genetic
engineering would be thinkable, there would be no coherent argument against it,
and we would be heading straight for Brave New World.
Pinker
doesn't realize what today's real problem is. The theory of the blank slate
promoted totalitarianism in the past, when human nature was an obstacle to
utopian schemes. But today, we are developing the ability to control human
nature, and Pinker's physicalism removes the best reason to stop totalitarians
from changing human nature to fit it into their utopian schemes.
In the
future, as we gain more and more power to control human nature, Marx's
dialectical materialism will not be as great a threat to freedom as Pinker's
physicalist materialism.